Techno Blender
Digitally Yours.

Towards Geometric Deep Learning I: On the Shoulders of Giants | by Michael Bronstein | Jul, 2022

0 90


Geometric Deep Learning approaches a broad class of ML problems from the perspectives of symmetry and invariance, providing a common blueprint for neural network architectures as diverse as CNNs, GNNs, and Transformers. In a new series of posts, we study how these ideas have emerged through history from ancient Greek geometry to Graph Neural Networks.

Image: based on Shutterstock.

What is in common between snowflakes and the Standard Model? Symmetry. In the first post from the “Towards Geometric Deep Learning series,” we discuss how the concept of symmetry has helped organise the zoo of nineteenth-century geometries and revolutionise theoretical physics. This post is based on the introduction chapter of the book M. M. Bronstein, J. Bruna, T. Cohen, and P. Veličković, Geometric Deep Learning (to appear with MIT Press upon completion) and accompanies our course in the African Masters in Machine Intelligence (AMMI). See our previous post summarising the concept of Geometric Deep Learning.

The last decade has witnessed an experimental revolution in data science and machine learning, epitomised by deep learning methods. Indeed, many high-dimensional learning tasks previously thought to be beyond reach — computer vision, playing Go, or protein folding — are in fact feasible with appropriate computational scale. Remarkably, the essence of deep learning is built from two simple algorithmic principles: first, the notion of representation or feature learning, whereby adapted, often hierarchical, features capture the appropriate notion of regularity for each task, and second, learning by gradient descent-type optimisation, typically implemented as backpropagation.

While learning generic functions in high dimensions is a cursed estimation problem, most tasks of interest are not generic and come with essential predefined regularities arising from the underlying low-dimensionality and structure of the physical world. Geometric Deep Learning is concerned with exposing these regularities through unified geometric principles that can be applied throughout a broad spectrum of applications.

Exploiting the known symmetries of a large system is a powerful and classical remedy against the curse of dimensionality, and forms the basis of most physical theories. Deep learning systems are no exception, and since the early days, researchers have adapted neural networks to exploit the low-dimensional geometry arising from physical measurements, e.g. grids in images, sequences in time-series, or position and momentum in molecules, and their associated symmetries, such as translation or rotation.

Since these ideas have deep roots in science, we will attempt to see how they have evolved throughout history, culminating in a common blueprint that can be applied to most of today’s popular neural network architectures.

“Symmetry, as wide or as narrow as you may define its meaning, is one idea by which man through the ages has tried to comprehend and create order, beauty, and perfection.” — Hermann Weyl (1952)

This somewhat poetic definition of symmetry is given in the eponymous book of the great mathematician Hermann Weyl [1], his Schwanengesang on the eve of retirement from the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton. Weyl traces the special place symmetry has occupied in science and art to the ancient times, from Sumerian symmetric designs to the Pythagoreans, who believed the circle to be perfect due to its rotational symmetry. Plato considered the five regular polyhedra bearing his name today so fundamental that they must be the basic building blocks shaping the material world.

Yet, though Plato is credited with coining the term συμμετρία, which literally translates as ‘same measure’, he used it only vaguely to convey the beauty of proportion in art and harmony in music. It was the German astronomer and mathematician Johannes Kepler to attempt the first rigorous analysis of the symmetric shape of water crystals. In his treatise ‘On the Six-Cornered Snowflake’ [2], he attributed the six-fold dihedral structure of snowflakes to
hexagonal packing of particles — an idea that though preceded the clear understanding of how matter is formed, still holds today as the basis of crystallography [3].

Plato (left) believed that symmetric polyhedra (“Platonic solids”) were the fundamental building blocks of Nature. Johannes Kepler (right) attributed for the first time the six-fold symmetry of water crystals to the hexagonal packing of particles, antedating modern crystallography.

In modern mathematics, symmetry is almost univocally expressed in the language of group theory. The origins of this theory are usually attributed to Évariste Galois, who coined the term and used it to study the solvability of polynomial equations in the 1830s [4]. Two other names associated with group theory are those of Sophus Lie and Felix Klein, who met and worked fruitfully together for a period of time [5]. The former would develop the theory of continuous symmetries that today bears his name (Lie groups); the latter proclaimed group theory to be the organising principle of geometry in his Erlangen Programme. Given that Klein’s Programme is the inspiration for Geometric Deep Learning, it is worthwhile to spend more time on its historical context and revolutionary impact.

Évariste Galois (left) and his letter to a friend describing group theory on the night before his fatal duel. Felix Klein (right) and the frontispiece of the research prospectus prepared for his professorial appointment, which has entered the history of mathematics as the “Erlangen Programme.” Klein’s portrait: Ihor Gorskiy.

The foundations of modern geometry were formalised in ancient Greece nearly 2300 years ago by Euclid in a treatise named the Elements. Euclidean geometry (which is still taught at school as ‘the geometry’) was a set of results built upon five intuitive axioms or postulates. The Fifth Postulate — stating that it is possible to pass only one line parallel to a given line through a point outside it — appeared less obvious and an illustrious row of mathematicians broke their teeth trying to prove it since antiquity, to no avail.

An early approach to the problem of the parallels appears in the eleventh-century Persian treatise ‘A commentary on the difficulties concerning the postulates of Euclid’s Elements’ by Omar Khayyam [6]. The eighteenth-century Italian Jesuit priest Giovanni Saccheri was likely aware of this previous work judging by the title of his own work Euclides ab omni nævo vindicatus (‘Euclid cleared of every stain’).

Like Khayyam, he considered the summit angles of a quadrilateral with sides perpendicular to the base. The conclusion that acute angles lead to infinitely many non-intersecting lines that can be passed through a point not on a straight line seemed so counter-intuitive that he rejected it as ‘repugnatis naturæ linæ rectæ’ (‘repugnant to the nature of straight lines’) [7].

Frontispiece of Giovanni Saccheri’s ‘Euclides vindicatus’ and the passage rejecting hyperbolic geometry as ‘repugnatis naturæ linæ rectæ.’

The nineteenth century has brought the realisation that the Fifth Postulate is not essential and one can construct alternative geometries based on different notions of parallelism. One such early example is projective geometry, arising, as the name suggests, in perspective drawing and architecture. In this geometry, points and lines are interchangeable, and there are no parallel lines in the usual sense: any lines meet in a ‘point at infinity.’ While results in projective geometry had been known since antiquity, it was first systematically studied by Jean-Victor Poncelet in 1812 [8].

The credit for the first construction of a true non-Euclidean geometry is disputed. The princeps mathematicorum Carl Friedrich Gauss worked on it around 1813 but never published any results [9]. The first publication on the subject of non-Euclidean geometry was ‘On the Origins of Geometry’ by the Russian mathematician Nikolai Lobachevsky [10]. In this work, he considered the Fifth Postulate an arbitrary limitation and proposed an alternative one, that more than one line can pass through a point that is parallel to a given one. Such construction requires a space with negative curvature — what we now call a hyperbolic space — a notion that was still not fully mastered at that time [11].

János Bolyai’s letter to his father in Hungarian dated 3 November 1823 (left), announcing his discovery of hyperbolic geometry. Nikolai Lobachevsky (right) and the first page of his work “On the Origins of Geometry,” published in 1829.

Lobachevsky’s idea appeared heretical and he was openly derided by colleagues [12]. A similar construction was independently discovered by the Hungarian János Bolyai, who published it in 1832 under the name ‘absolute geometry.’ In an earlier letter to his father dated 1823, he wrote enthusiastically about this new development:

“I have discovered such wonderful things that I was amazed… out of nothing I have created a strange new world.” — János Bolyai (1823)

In the meantime, new geometries continued to come out like from a cornucopia. August Möbius [13], of the eponymous surface fame, studied affine geometry. Gauss’ student Bernhardt Riemann introduced a very broad class of geometries — called today Riemannian is his honour — in his habilitation lecture, subsequently published under the title Über die Hypothesen, welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen (‘On the Hypotheses on which Geometry is Based’) [14]. A special case of Riemannian geometry is the ‘elliptic’ geometry of the sphere, another construction violating Euclid’s Fifth Postulate, as there is no point on the sphere through which a line can be drawn that never intersects a given line.

Towards the second half of the nineteenth century, Euclid’s monopoly over geometry was completely shuttered. New types of geometry (Euclidean, affine, projective, hyperbolic, spherical) emerged and became independent fields of study. However, the relationships of these geometries and their hierarchy were not understood.

It was in this exciting but messy situation that Felix Klein came forth, with a genius insight to use group theory as an algebraic abstraction of symmetry to organise the ‘geometric zoo.’ Only 23 years old at the time of his appointment as a professor in Erlangen, Klein, as it was customary in German universities, was requested to deliver an inaugural research programme — titled Vergleichende Betrachtungen über neuere geometrische Forschungen (‘A comparative review of recent researches in geometry’), it has entered the annals of mathematics as the “Erlangen Programme” [15].

The breakthrough insight of Klein was to approach the definition of geometry as the study of invariants, or in other words, structures that are preserved under a certain type of transformations (symmetries). Klein used the formalism of group theory to define such transformations and use the hierarchy of groups and their subgroups in order to classify different geometries arising from them.

Klein’s Erlangen Programme defined geometry as the space with a group of transformations. This allowed classifying different types of geometry.

It appeared that Euclidean geometry is a special case of affine geometry, which is in turn a special case of projective geometry (or, in terms of group theory, the Euclidean group is a subgroup of the projective group). Klein’s Erlangen Programme was in a sense the ‘second algebraisation’ of geometry (the first one being the analytic geometry of René Descartes and the method of coordinates bearing his Latinised name Cartesius) that allowed to produce results impossible by previous methods.

More general Riemannian geometry was explicitly excluded from Klein’s unified geometric picture, and it took another fifty years before it was integrated, largely thanks to the work of Élie Cartan in the 1920s. Furthermore, Category Theory, now pervasive in pure mathematics, can be “regarded as a continuation of the Klein Erlangen Programme, in the sense that a geometrical space with its group of transformations is generalized to a category with its algebra of mappings”, in the words of its creators Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane [16].

Considering projective geometry the most general of all, Klein complained in his Vergleichende Betrachtungen [17]:

“How persistently the mathematical physicist disregards the advantages afforded him in many cases by only a moderate cultivation of the projective view.” — Felix Klein (1872)

His advocating for the exploitation of geometry and the principles of symmetry in physics has foretold the following century that was truly revolutionary for the field.

In Göttingen [18], Klein’s colleague Emmy Noether [19] proved that every differentiable symmetry of the action of a physical system has a corresponding conservation law [20]. It was, by all means, a stunning result: beforehand, meticulous experimental observation was required to discover fundamental laws such as the conservation of energy, and even then, it was an empirical result not coming from anywhere. Noether’s Theorem — “a guiding star to 20th and 21st century physics,” in the words of the Nobel laureate Frank Wilczek — allowed for example to show that the conservation of energy emerges from the translational symmetry of time, a rather intuitive idea that the results of an experiment should not depend on whether
it is conducted today or tomorrow.

Hermann Weyl (left) and a 1918 postcard from Einstein arguing with his initially proposed gauge theory. Emmy Noether (right) and the publication from the same year containing her celebrated theorem. Noether’s portrait: Ihor Gorskiy.

Another symmetry associated with charge conservation, the global gauge invariance of the electromagnetic field, first appeared in Maxwell’s formulation of electrodynamics [21]; however, its importance initially remained unnoticed. The same Hermann Weyl, who wrote so dithyrambically about symmetry, is the one who first introduced the concept of gauge invariance in physics in the early 20th century [22], emphasizing its role as a principle from which electromagnetism can be derived. It took several decades until this fundamental principle — in its generalised form developed by Yang and Mills [23] — proved successful in providing a unified framework to describe the quantum-mechanical behaviour of electromagnetism and the weak and strong forces, finally culminating in the Standard Model that captures all the fundamental forces of nature but gravity. As succinctly put by another Nobel-winning physicist, Philip Anderson [24],

“it is only slightly overstating the case to say that physics is the study of symmetry” — Philip Anderson (1972)

[1] H. Weyl, Symmetry (1952), Princeton University Press.

[2] Fully titled Strena, Seu De Nive Sexangula (’New Year’s gift, or on the Six-Cornered Snowflake’) was, as suggested by the title, a small booklet sent by Kepler in 1611 as a Christmas gift to his patron and friend Johannes Matthäus Wackher von Wackenfels.

[3] P. Ball, In retrospect: On the six-cornered snowflake (2011), Nature 480 (7378):455–455.

[4] Galois famously described the ideas of group theory (which he considered in the context of finding solutions to polynomial equations) and coined the term “group” (groupe in French) in a letter to a friend written on the eve of his fatal duel. He asked to communicate his ideas to prominent mathematicians of the time, expressing the hope that they would be able to “‘decipher all this mess’” (“‘déchiffrer tout ce gâchis”). Galois died two days later from wounds suffered in the duel aged only 20, but his work has been transformational in mathematics.

[5] See biographic notes in R. Tobies, Felix Klein — Mathematician, Academic Organizer, Educational Reformer (2019), The Legacy of Felix Klein 5–21, Springer.

[6] Omar Khayyam is nowadays mainly remembered as a poet and author of the immortal line “‘a flask of wine, a book of verse, and thou beside me.”

[7] The publication of Euclides vindicatus required the approval of the Inquisition, which came in 1733 just a few months before the author’s death. Rediscovered by the Italian differential geometer Eugenio Beltrami in the nineteenth century, Saccheri’s work is now considered an early almost-successful attempt to construct hyperbolic geometry.

[8] Poncelet was a military engineer and participant in Napoleon’s Russian campaign, where he was captured and held as a prisoner until the end of the war. It was during this captivity period that he wrote the Traité des propriétés
projectives des figures
(‘Treatise on the projective properties of figures,’ 1822) that revived the interest in projective geometry. Earlier foundation work on this subject was done by his compatriot Gérard Desargues in 1643.

[9] In the 1832 letter to Farkas Bolyai following the publication of his son’s results, Gauss famously wrote: “To praise it would amount to praising myself. For the entire content of the work coincides almost exactly with my own meditations which have occupied my mind for the past thirty or thirty-five years.” Gauss was also the first to use the term ‘non-Euclidean geometry,’ referring strictu sensu to his own construction of hyperbolic geometry. See
R. L. Faber, Foundations of Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometry (1983), Dekker and the blog post in Cantor’s Paradise.

[10] Н. И. Лобачевский, О началах геометрии (1829).

[11] A model for hyperbolic geometry known as the pseudosphere, a surface with constant negative curvature, was shown by Eugenio Beltrami, who also proved that hyperbolic geometry was logically consistent. The term ‘hyperbolic geometry’ was introduced by Felix Klein.

[12] For example, an 1834 pamphlet signed only with the initials “S.S.” (believed by some to belong to Lobachevsky’s long-time opponent Ostrogradsky) claimed that Lobachevsky made “an obscure and heavy theory” out of “the lightest and clearest chapter of mathematics, geometry,” wondered why one would print such “ridiculous fantasies,” and suggested that the book was a “joke or satire.”

[13] A. F. Möbius, Der barycentrische Calcul (1827).

[14] B. Riemann, Über die Hypothesen, welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen (1854). See English translation.

[15] According to a popular belief, repeated in many sources including Wikipedia, the Erlangen Programme was delivered in Klein’s inaugural address in October 1872. Klein indeed gave such a talk (though on December 7, 1872), but it was for a non-mathematical audience and concerned primarily his ideas of mathematical education; see[4]. The name “Programme” comes from the subtitle of the published brochure [17], Programm zum Eintritt in die philosophische Fakultät und den Senat der k. Friedrich-Alexanders-Universität zu Erlangen (‘Programme for entry into the Philosophical Faculty and the Senate of the Emperor Friedrich-Alexander University of Erlangen’).

[16] S. Eilenberg and S. MacLane, General theory of natural equivalences (1945), Trans. AMS 58(2):231–294. See also J.-P. Marquis, Category Theory and Klein’s Erlangen Program (2009), From a Geometrical Point of View 9–40, Springer.

[17] F. Klein, Vergleichende Betrachtungen über neuere geometrische Forschungen (1872). See English translation.

[18] At the time, Göttingen was Germany’s and the world’s leading centre of mathematics. Though Erlangen is proud of its association with Klein, he stayed there for only three years, moving in 1875 to the Technical University of Munich (then called Technische Hochschule), followed by Leipzig (1880), and finally settling down in Göttingen from 1886 until his retirement.

[19] Emmy Noether is rightfully regarded as one of the most important women in mathematics and one of the greatest mathematicians of the twentieth century. She was unlucky to be born and live in an epoch when the academic world was still entrenched in the medieval beliefs of the unsuitability of women for science. Her career as one of the few women in mathematics having to overcome prejudice and contempt was a truly trailblazing one. It should be said to the credit of her male colleagues that some of them tried to break the rules. When Klein and David Hilbert first unsuccessfully attempted to secure a teaching position for Noether at Göttingen, they met fierce opposition from the academic hierarchs. Hilbert reportedly retorted sarcastically to concerns brought up in one such discussion: “I do not see that the sex of the candidate is an argument against her admission as a Privatdozent. After all, the Senate is not a bathhouse”(see C. Reid, Courant in Göttingen and New York: The Story of an Improbable Mathematician (1976), Springer). Nevertheless, Noether enjoyed great esteem among her close collaborators and students, and her male peers in Göttingen affectionately referred to her as “Der Noether,” in the masculine (see C. Quigg, Colloquium: A Century of Noether’s Theorem (2019), arXiv:1902.01989).

[20] E. Noether, Invariante Variationsprobleme (1918), König Gesellsch. d. Wiss. zu Göttingen, Math-Phys. 235–257. See English translation.

[21] J. C. Maxwell, A dynamical theory of the electromagnetic field (1865), Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London 155:459–512.

[22] Weyl first conjectured (incorrectly) in 1919 that invariance under the change of scale or “gauge” was a local symmetry of electromagnetism. The term gauge, or Eich in German, was chosen by analogy to the various track gauges of railroads. After the development of quantum mechanics, he modified the gauge choice by replacing the scale factor with a change of wave phase in iH. Weyl, Elektron und gravitation (1929), Zeitschrift für Physik 56 (5–6): 330–352. See N. Straumann, Early history of gauge theories and weak interactions (1996), arXiv:hep-ph/9609230.

[23] C.-N. Yang and R. L. Mills, Conservation of isotopic spin and isotopic gauge invariance (1954), Physical Review 96 (1):191.

[24] P. W. Anderson, More is different (1972), Science 177 (4047): 393–396.


Geometric Deep Learning approaches a broad class of ML problems from the perspectives of symmetry and invariance, providing a common blueprint for neural network architectures as diverse as CNNs, GNNs, and Transformers. In a new series of posts, we study how these ideas have emerged through history from ancient Greek geometry to Graph Neural Networks.

Image: based on Shutterstock.

What is in common between snowflakes and the Standard Model? Symmetry. In the first post from the “Towards Geometric Deep Learning series,” we discuss how the concept of symmetry has helped organise the zoo of nineteenth-century geometries and revolutionise theoretical physics. This post is based on the introduction chapter of the book M. M. Bronstein, J. Bruna, T. Cohen, and P. Veličković, Geometric Deep Learning (to appear with MIT Press upon completion) and accompanies our course in the African Masters in Machine Intelligence (AMMI). See our previous post summarising the concept of Geometric Deep Learning.

The last decade has witnessed an experimental revolution in data science and machine learning, epitomised by deep learning methods. Indeed, many high-dimensional learning tasks previously thought to be beyond reach — computer vision, playing Go, or protein folding — are in fact feasible with appropriate computational scale. Remarkably, the essence of deep learning is built from two simple algorithmic principles: first, the notion of representation or feature learning, whereby adapted, often hierarchical, features capture the appropriate notion of regularity for each task, and second, learning by gradient descent-type optimisation, typically implemented as backpropagation.

While learning generic functions in high dimensions is a cursed estimation problem, most tasks of interest are not generic and come with essential predefined regularities arising from the underlying low-dimensionality and structure of the physical world. Geometric Deep Learning is concerned with exposing these regularities through unified geometric principles that can be applied throughout a broad spectrum of applications.

Exploiting the known symmetries of a large system is a powerful and classical remedy against the curse of dimensionality, and forms the basis of most physical theories. Deep learning systems are no exception, and since the early days, researchers have adapted neural networks to exploit the low-dimensional geometry arising from physical measurements, e.g. grids in images, sequences in time-series, or position and momentum in molecules, and their associated symmetries, such as translation or rotation.

Since these ideas have deep roots in science, we will attempt to see how they have evolved throughout history, culminating in a common blueprint that can be applied to most of today’s popular neural network architectures.

“Symmetry, as wide or as narrow as you may define its meaning, is one idea by which man through the ages has tried to comprehend and create order, beauty, and perfection.” — Hermann Weyl (1952)

This somewhat poetic definition of symmetry is given in the eponymous book of the great mathematician Hermann Weyl [1], his Schwanengesang on the eve of retirement from the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton. Weyl traces the special place symmetry has occupied in science and art to the ancient times, from Sumerian symmetric designs to the Pythagoreans, who believed the circle to be perfect due to its rotational symmetry. Plato considered the five regular polyhedra bearing his name today so fundamental that they must be the basic building blocks shaping the material world.

Yet, though Plato is credited with coining the term συμμετρία, which literally translates as ‘same measure’, he used it only vaguely to convey the beauty of proportion in art and harmony in music. It was the German astronomer and mathematician Johannes Kepler to attempt the first rigorous analysis of the symmetric shape of water crystals. In his treatise ‘On the Six-Cornered Snowflake’ [2], he attributed the six-fold dihedral structure of snowflakes to
hexagonal packing of particles — an idea that though preceded the clear understanding of how matter is formed, still holds today as the basis of crystallography [3].

Plato (left) believed that symmetric polyhedra (“Platonic solids”) were the fundamental building blocks of Nature. Johannes Kepler (right) attributed for the first time the six-fold symmetry of water crystals to the hexagonal packing of particles, antedating modern crystallography.

In modern mathematics, symmetry is almost univocally expressed in the language of group theory. The origins of this theory are usually attributed to Évariste Galois, who coined the term and used it to study the solvability of polynomial equations in the 1830s [4]. Two other names associated with group theory are those of Sophus Lie and Felix Klein, who met and worked fruitfully together for a period of time [5]. The former would develop the theory of continuous symmetries that today bears his name (Lie groups); the latter proclaimed group theory to be the organising principle of geometry in his Erlangen Programme. Given that Klein’s Programme is the inspiration for Geometric Deep Learning, it is worthwhile to spend more time on its historical context and revolutionary impact.

Évariste Galois (left) and his letter to a friend describing group theory on the night before his fatal duel. Felix Klein (right) and the frontispiece of the research prospectus prepared for his professorial appointment, which has entered the history of mathematics as the “Erlangen Programme.” Klein’s portrait: Ihor Gorskiy.

The foundations of modern geometry were formalised in ancient Greece nearly 2300 years ago by Euclid in a treatise named the Elements. Euclidean geometry (which is still taught at school as ‘the geometry’) was a set of results built upon five intuitive axioms or postulates. The Fifth Postulate — stating that it is possible to pass only one line parallel to a given line through a point outside it — appeared less obvious and an illustrious row of mathematicians broke their teeth trying to prove it since antiquity, to no avail.

An early approach to the problem of the parallels appears in the eleventh-century Persian treatise ‘A commentary on the difficulties concerning the postulates of Euclid’s Elements’ by Omar Khayyam [6]. The eighteenth-century Italian Jesuit priest Giovanni Saccheri was likely aware of this previous work judging by the title of his own work Euclides ab omni nævo vindicatus (‘Euclid cleared of every stain’).

Like Khayyam, he considered the summit angles of a quadrilateral with sides perpendicular to the base. The conclusion that acute angles lead to infinitely many non-intersecting lines that can be passed through a point not on a straight line seemed so counter-intuitive that he rejected it as ‘repugnatis naturæ linæ rectæ’ (‘repugnant to the nature of straight lines’) [7].

Frontispiece of Giovanni Saccheri’s ‘Euclides vindicatus’ and the passage rejecting hyperbolic geometry as ‘repugnatis naturæ linæ rectæ.’

The nineteenth century has brought the realisation that the Fifth Postulate is not essential and one can construct alternative geometries based on different notions of parallelism. One such early example is projective geometry, arising, as the name suggests, in perspective drawing and architecture. In this geometry, points and lines are interchangeable, and there are no parallel lines in the usual sense: any lines meet in a ‘point at infinity.’ While results in projective geometry had been known since antiquity, it was first systematically studied by Jean-Victor Poncelet in 1812 [8].

The credit for the first construction of a true non-Euclidean geometry is disputed. The princeps mathematicorum Carl Friedrich Gauss worked on it around 1813 but never published any results [9]. The first publication on the subject of non-Euclidean geometry was ‘On the Origins of Geometry’ by the Russian mathematician Nikolai Lobachevsky [10]. In this work, he considered the Fifth Postulate an arbitrary limitation and proposed an alternative one, that more than one line can pass through a point that is parallel to a given one. Such construction requires a space with negative curvature — what we now call a hyperbolic space — a notion that was still not fully mastered at that time [11].

János Bolyai’s letter to his father in Hungarian dated 3 November 1823 (left), announcing his discovery of hyperbolic geometry. Nikolai Lobachevsky (right) and the first page of his work “On the Origins of Geometry,” published in 1829.

Lobachevsky’s idea appeared heretical and he was openly derided by colleagues [12]. A similar construction was independently discovered by the Hungarian János Bolyai, who published it in 1832 under the name ‘absolute geometry.’ In an earlier letter to his father dated 1823, he wrote enthusiastically about this new development:

“I have discovered such wonderful things that I was amazed… out of nothing I have created a strange new world.” — János Bolyai (1823)

In the meantime, new geometries continued to come out like from a cornucopia. August Möbius [13], of the eponymous surface fame, studied affine geometry. Gauss’ student Bernhardt Riemann introduced a very broad class of geometries — called today Riemannian is his honour — in his habilitation lecture, subsequently published under the title Über die Hypothesen, welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen (‘On the Hypotheses on which Geometry is Based’) [14]. A special case of Riemannian geometry is the ‘elliptic’ geometry of the sphere, another construction violating Euclid’s Fifth Postulate, as there is no point on the sphere through which a line can be drawn that never intersects a given line.

Towards the second half of the nineteenth century, Euclid’s monopoly over geometry was completely shuttered. New types of geometry (Euclidean, affine, projective, hyperbolic, spherical) emerged and became independent fields of study. However, the relationships of these geometries and their hierarchy were not understood.

It was in this exciting but messy situation that Felix Klein came forth, with a genius insight to use group theory as an algebraic abstraction of symmetry to organise the ‘geometric zoo.’ Only 23 years old at the time of his appointment as a professor in Erlangen, Klein, as it was customary in German universities, was requested to deliver an inaugural research programme — titled Vergleichende Betrachtungen über neuere geometrische Forschungen (‘A comparative review of recent researches in geometry’), it has entered the annals of mathematics as the “Erlangen Programme” [15].

The breakthrough insight of Klein was to approach the definition of geometry as the study of invariants, or in other words, structures that are preserved under a certain type of transformations (symmetries). Klein used the formalism of group theory to define such transformations and use the hierarchy of groups and their subgroups in order to classify different geometries arising from them.

Klein’s Erlangen Programme defined geometry as the space with a group of transformations. This allowed classifying different types of geometry.

It appeared that Euclidean geometry is a special case of affine geometry, which is in turn a special case of projective geometry (or, in terms of group theory, the Euclidean group is a subgroup of the projective group). Klein’s Erlangen Programme was in a sense the ‘second algebraisation’ of geometry (the first one being the analytic geometry of René Descartes and the method of coordinates bearing his Latinised name Cartesius) that allowed to produce results impossible by previous methods.

More general Riemannian geometry was explicitly excluded from Klein’s unified geometric picture, and it took another fifty years before it was integrated, largely thanks to the work of Élie Cartan in the 1920s. Furthermore, Category Theory, now pervasive in pure mathematics, can be “regarded as a continuation of the Klein Erlangen Programme, in the sense that a geometrical space with its group of transformations is generalized to a category with its algebra of mappings”, in the words of its creators Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane [16].

Considering projective geometry the most general of all, Klein complained in his Vergleichende Betrachtungen [17]:

“How persistently the mathematical physicist disregards the advantages afforded him in many cases by only a moderate cultivation of the projective view.” — Felix Klein (1872)

His advocating for the exploitation of geometry and the principles of symmetry in physics has foretold the following century that was truly revolutionary for the field.

In Göttingen [18], Klein’s colleague Emmy Noether [19] proved that every differentiable symmetry of the action of a physical system has a corresponding conservation law [20]. It was, by all means, a stunning result: beforehand, meticulous experimental observation was required to discover fundamental laws such as the conservation of energy, and even then, it was an empirical result not coming from anywhere. Noether’s Theorem — “a guiding star to 20th and 21st century physics,” in the words of the Nobel laureate Frank Wilczek — allowed for example to show that the conservation of energy emerges from the translational symmetry of time, a rather intuitive idea that the results of an experiment should not depend on whether
it is conducted today or tomorrow.

Hermann Weyl (left) and a 1918 postcard from Einstein arguing with his initially proposed gauge theory. Emmy Noether (right) and the publication from the same year containing her celebrated theorem. Noether’s portrait: Ihor Gorskiy.

Another symmetry associated with charge conservation, the global gauge invariance of the electromagnetic field, first appeared in Maxwell’s formulation of electrodynamics [21]; however, its importance initially remained unnoticed. The same Hermann Weyl, who wrote so dithyrambically about symmetry, is the one who first introduced the concept of gauge invariance in physics in the early 20th century [22], emphasizing its role as a principle from which electromagnetism can be derived. It took several decades until this fundamental principle — in its generalised form developed by Yang and Mills [23] — proved successful in providing a unified framework to describe the quantum-mechanical behaviour of electromagnetism and the weak and strong forces, finally culminating in the Standard Model that captures all the fundamental forces of nature but gravity. As succinctly put by another Nobel-winning physicist, Philip Anderson [24],

“it is only slightly overstating the case to say that physics is the study of symmetry” — Philip Anderson (1972)

[1] H. Weyl, Symmetry (1952), Princeton University Press.

[2] Fully titled Strena, Seu De Nive Sexangula (’New Year’s gift, or on the Six-Cornered Snowflake’) was, as suggested by the title, a small booklet sent by Kepler in 1611 as a Christmas gift to his patron and friend Johannes Matthäus Wackher von Wackenfels.

[3] P. Ball, In retrospect: On the six-cornered snowflake (2011), Nature 480 (7378):455–455.

[4] Galois famously described the ideas of group theory (which he considered in the context of finding solutions to polynomial equations) and coined the term “group” (groupe in French) in a letter to a friend written on the eve of his fatal duel. He asked to communicate his ideas to prominent mathematicians of the time, expressing the hope that they would be able to “‘decipher all this mess’” (“‘déchiffrer tout ce gâchis”). Galois died two days later from wounds suffered in the duel aged only 20, but his work has been transformational in mathematics.

[5] See biographic notes in R. Tobies, Felix Klein — Mathematician, Academic Organizer, Educational Reformer (2019), The Legacy of Felix Klein 5–21, Springer.

[6] Omar Khayyam is nowadays mainly remembered as a poet and author of the immortal line “‘a flask of wine, a book of verse, and thou beside me.”

[7] The publication of Euclides vindicatus required the approval of the Inquisition, which came in 1733 just a few months before the author’s death. Rediscovered by the Italian differential geometer Eugenio Beltrami in the nineteenth century, Saccheri’s work is now considered an early almost-successful attempt to construct hyperbolic geometry.

[8] Poncelet was a military engineer and participant in Napoleon’s Russian campaign, where he was captured and held as a prisoner until the end of the war. It was during this captivity period that he wrote the Traité des propriétés
projectives des figures
(‘Treatise on the projective properties of figures,’ 1822) that revived the interest in projective geometry. Earlier foundation work on this subject was done by his compatriot Gérard Desargues in 1643.

[9] In the 1832 letter to Farkas Bolyai following the publication of his son’s results, Gauss famously wrote: “To praise it would amount to praising myself. For the entire content of the work coincides almost exactly with my own meditations which have occupied my mind for the past thirty or thirty-five years.” Gauss was also the first to use the term ‘non-Euclidean geometry,’ referring strictu sensu to his own construction of hyperbolic geometry. See
R. L. Faber, Foundations of Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometry (1983), Dekker and the blog post in Cantor’s Paradise.

[10] Н. И. Лобачевский, О началах геометрии (1829).

[11] A model for hyperbolic geometry known as the pseudosphere, a surface with constant negative curvature, was shown by Eugenio Beltrami, who also proved that hyperbolic geometry was logically consistent. The term ‘hyperbolic geometry’ was introduced by Felix Klein.

[12] For example, an 1834 pamphlet signed only with the initials “S.S.” (believed by some to belong to Lobachevsky’s long-time opponent Ostrogradsky) claimed that Lobachevsky made “an obscure and heavy theory” out of “the lightest and clearest chapter of mathematics, geometry,” wondered why one would print such “ridiculous fantasies,” and suggested that the book was a “joke or satire.”

[13] A. F. Möbius, Der barycentrische Calcul (1827).

[14] B. Riemann, Über die Hypothesen, welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen (1854). See English translation.

[15] According to a popular belief, repeated in many sources including Wikipedia, the Erlangen Programme was delivered in Klein’s inaugural address in October 1872. Klein indeed gave such a talk (though on December 7, 1872), but it was for a non-mathematical audience and concerned primarily his ideas of mathematical education; see[4]. The name “Programme” comes from the subtitle of the published brochure [17], Programm zum Eintritt in die philosophische Fakultät und den Senat der k. Friedrich-Alexanders-Universität zu Erlangen (‘Programme for entry into the Philosophical Faculty and the Senate of the Emperor Friedrich-Alexander University of Erlangen’).

[16] S. Eilenberg and S. MacLane, General theory of natural equivalences (1945), Trans. AMS 58(2):231–294. See also J.-P. Marquis, Category Theory and Klein’s Erlangen Program (2009), From a Geometrical Point of View 9–40, Springer.

[17] F. Klein, Vergleichende Betrachtungen über neuere geometrische Forschungen (1872). See English translation.

[18] At the time, Göttingen was Germany’s and the world’s leading centre of mathematics. Though Erlangen is proud of its association with Klein, he stayed there for only three years, moving in 1875 to the Technical University of Munich (then called Technische Hochschule), followed by Leipzig (1880), and finally settling down in Göttingen from 1886 until his retirement.

[19] Emmy Noether is rightfully regarded as one of the most important women in mathematics and one of the greatest mathematicians of the twentieth century. She was unlucky to be born and live in an epoch when the academic world was still entrenched in the medieval beliefs of the unsuitability of women for science. Her career as one of the few women in mathematics having to overcome prejudice and contempt was a truly trailblazing one. It should be said to the credit of her male colleagues that some of them tried to break the rules. When Klein and David Hilbert first unsuccessfully attempted to secure a teaching position for Noether at Göttingen, they met fierce opposition from the academic hierarchs. Hilbert reportedly retorted sarcastically to concerns brought up in one such discussion: “I do not see that the sex of the candidate is an argument against her admission as a Privatdozent. After all, the Senate is not a bathhouse”(see C. Reid, Courant in Göttingen and New York: The Story of an Improbable Mathematician (1976), Springer). Nevertheless, Noether enjoyed great esteem among her close collaborators and students, and her male peers in Göttingen affectionately referred to her as “Der Noether,” in the masculine (see C. Quigg, Colloquium: A Century of Noether’s Theorem (2019), arXiv:1902.01989).

[20] E. Noether, Invariante Variationsprobleme (1918), König Gesellsch. d. Wiss. zu Göttingen, Math-Phys. 235–257. See English translation.

[21] J. C. Maxwell, A dynamical theory of the electromagnetic field (1865), Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London 155:459–512.

[22] Weyl first conjectured (incorrectly) in 1919 that invariance under the change of scale or “gauge” was a local symmetry of electromagnetism. The term gauge, or Eich in German, was chosen by analogy to the various track gauges of railroads. After the development of quantum mechanics, he modified the gauge choice by replacing the scale factor with a change of wave phase in iH. Weyl, Elektron und gravitation (1929), Zeitschrift für Physik 56 (5–6): 330–352. See N. Straumann, Early history of gauge theories and weak interactions (1996), arXiv:hep-ph/9609230.

[23] C.-N. Yang and R. L. Mills, Conservation of isotopic spin and isotopic gauge invariance (1954), Physical Review 96 (1):191.

[24] P. W. Anderson, More is different (1972), Science 177 (4047): 393–396.

FOLLOW US ON GOOGLE NEWS

Read original article here

Denial of responsibility! Techno Blender is an automatic aggregator of the all world’s media. In each content, the hyperlink to the primary source is specified. All trademarks belong to their rightful owners, all materials to their authors. If you are the owner of the content and do not want us to publish your materials, please contact us by email – [email protected]. The content will be deleted within 24 hours.
Leave a comment